8/10/2006

Human Language and the Divine

Over the last several months–and especially within the last few days–I have been involved in numerous conversations about the nature and function of human language in describing God. What follows is not meant to be a fully-developed essay, but is rather intended to be somewhat of a summary of the lines of thinking I have pursued and the very tentative conclusions which I have reached.

Obviously, one of the most prescient issues is to what extent one can affirm that human language is capable of literally expressing and/or encapsulating truth about the nature of God. The initial, and I believe correct, answer is that human language is insufficient to do this. After all, we are speaking about a finite medium (human language) through which we attempt to speak about that which is infinite. To use a material example, such would be like the proverbial two-dimensional Flatlander attempting to shake the hand of the three-dimensional invader of the two-dimensional plane. While the Flatlander may be able to intersect a two-dimensional cross-section of the three-dimensional visitor, the Flatlander will be, by virtue of his “difference,” incapable of fully engaging or encapsulating the reality of his new higher-dimensional friend. In a similar and more profound way, it is not possible that human language could somehow directly and fully engage the reality of the divine.

Despite this obvious conclusion, we persist in the attempt. Our language en toto, but also (and more) specifically in relation to the divine, is filled with propositional, absolutized words, phrases and linguistic expressions. This is, in actuality, unavoidable. After all, language, by its very nature, is absolutizing. To speak is to form and reflect some conception of the world. While the appropriateness of the linguistic symbols attached to the meanings being expressed may be questioned, it is clear that to speak is to construct; to speak is to make a declaration about the nature and meaning of the reality which one perceives.

The problem with the necessity of this functional reality in human language is that human language is necessarily self-referential. In the act of speaking, the content of language is rooted in that which we know. We cannot speak of that which we do not know, and that which we do know determines the shape and form of our language. An interesting example of this is Anselm’s “proof” for the existence of God. While the full argument will not be pursued here, the basic thrust of Anselm’s argument is that God is the “being than which no greater being can be conceived.” In essence, Anselm argument is two-fold: Humans have an idea of a perfect being–God. Concomitantly, human beings are not perfect. Therefore, to Anselm, the fact that finite, imperfect humans have a conception of a perfect being lends evidence to the fact that this perfect being–God–does, in fact, exist.

As history relates, Anselm’s argument was quickly dismantled by his antagonists. Guanilo, for example, mocked Anselm’s theory by using the example of “the perfect island,” asserting that the mere imagining of a “perfect island” by no means necessitates or proves its existence. However, what both Anselm and Guanilo miss is that it is the function and nature of human language—not the limitations of human epistemology—which renders Anselm’s argument moot.

Consider Anselm’s statement about God: “God is the being than whom no greater being can be imagined.” The beginning problem with such a proposition is that its very criterion is dependent upon human language. Determining the attributes of “greatest of all beings” requires an appeal to human descriptive language, and the greatness of God is delineated on the basis of these stated attributes. However, how does human language gain access to these attributes? Again, the very categorizing of properly “divine” attributes is dependent upon the absolutizing of human language about, suprise suprise!, human attributes. In this sense, the language by which one describes God is not truly reflective of the divine nature in an absolute sense, but is merely the infinitized form of human language about human experience. In such a scenario, God, at best, is the “biggest human,” or, at worst, has an existence dependent upon human consciousness.

The obvious dilemma that this creates is that propositionalizing about God necessitates a functional, if not actual, affirmation of the eternality of that which is “other” than God. After all, if God is said to be “such and such” litany of attributes that are merely the infinitized and absolutized versions of human attributes, there is no possible way in which to speak about God apart from that which God is affirmed to have created. In this sense, the Creator is dependent upon the creation, if nothing else, to simply exist within human language.

Another more generic example would be the biblical language of “God is love.” The truthfulness of this statement is not disputed by many, and any objections would not be to the linguistic construction of the statement, but would rather proceed along the lines of arguing that God is “x” other than “love.” However, if we look at the utilization of the language in this propositional statement, the anthropologically absolutizing nature of human language is seen to be deviously present. If one says, “God is love,” the presence of the qualifier “is” represents that a comparison is being made---the nature of “God” is delineated by the qualifier “love.” Alternatively, the phraseology of the statement could be just as accurately deployed as follows: “God exhibits all those characteristics and/or is composed (in nature) in such a way that God can be said to be equivalent, or wholly like unto the characteristics and/or composition (in nature) of love.”

Do we see what has happened in this statement, however? In the attempt to propositionalize about God, we have alternatively asserted that there is something to which God can be compared. But by necessity, if there is something by which the character of God can be adjudicated, we must naturally conclude that this qualifier is independent in nature from God and/or greater than or equal to God such that it is appropriate that God be likened unto “x.” In the case of the propositional statement, “God is love,” our linguistic construction, if literalized, affirms that this category of “love” is conceived to exist in such a way that it can be taken independently of God, and that God may be spoken of as fulfilling, in nature, the particular characteristics which would create the propriety of equating God with the property of love.

The above is said not for the intention of evacuating all meaning from phrases such as “God is love.” On a practical, functional level, it would seem apparent that the affirmation of “God is love” is not meant to convey that God is equal in nature (and substance?) to an independent property such as “love.” Rather, the phrase is deployed simply as a description–i.e., we have a notion of “love” and conceptualize God to be the height and, in fact, source of the same.

At the same time, however, this brief examination of human language in relation to the divine does highlight an important consideration: that is, we must always use extreme caution in how definitively and propositionally we affirm human language to encapsulate or even represent truth-statements about the divine nature. As our language will always fall short, simply by virtue of its finitude and anthropocentric nature, we cannot uncritically deploy language about the divine while concomitantly assuming that we have spoken something absolute or truth-encapsulating.

Conclusion

If the above-referenced lines of thinking are reasonable, how then should we pursue language about the divine? In closing, I would offer two suggestions.

1.) Our language must allow that God has existence apart from human language and experience. While this may seem like a foregone conclusion, the ways in which we deploy language about the divine often betrays this fact. If our language, and subsequent theologizing, cannot rise above (or below, as it may be) the tendency to resolve the divine upon the altars of linguistic absolutization and propositionalizing, we will forever speak only of ourselves; God will be merely a linguistic category that contains the trumped up self-evaluation of the human ego.

2.) Counter-intuitively enough, I believe the first suggestion is resolved in the second, that is, that our language of the divine must be thoroughly Christological. As Christians affirm, Christ, the eternal Logos of God as Incarnate in the person of Jesus, is the self-revelation of God. Yet interestingly enough, this self-revelation of the divine occurs on the level of human finitude, a level of messiness, imprecision, and contradictoriness. While the Incarnate nature of God’s self-revelation will certainly heighten the temptation for anthropologically exclusive language about the divine, it will also, if pursued circumspectly, mitigate significantly against the same, for any “sure” propositionalizing about the divine, eternal nature will require consideration of a bloody cross.

Before letting off, I must extend my thanks to Tim for spurring some of these ideas in my brain. For some interesting posts that he has made on these issues, see this post, as well as this one.

10 comments:

Austin said...

Exist,

I'm curious. Seeing that you have a profound suspicion of the ability for human language to acurately describe God, how can you justify any knowledge about Him, and in particular Jesus. What if the apostles were all wrong? If language is really as deficient as you suggest, how can we even be sure who the real Jesus is?

Is it possible that God decided to make Himself known acurately through human language, even if it isn't comprehensive?

Exist-Dissolve said...

austin--

Thanks for the comments.

I'm curious. Seeing that you have a profound suspicion of the ability for human language to acurately describe God, how can you justify any knowledge about Him, and in particular Jesus. What if the apostles were all wrong? If language is really as deficient as you suggest, how can we even be sure who the real Jesus is?

We can't be "sure" of who the real Jesus is in the sense of being able to lay out a litany of proofs that incontrivertably substantiate the hope and beliefs that we hold. However, it is this very "need" for proof that my post is directed against, for it is obvious that even in (or perhaps especially in...) religious-speak we utilize language not so much to express truth as much as we do to create a power and authority base from which we can proceed to propositionalize.

This is why, of course, faith is not rationalizing or calculating the probability of something being "true," but is rather the anti- and, concomitantly supra-"rational" move that resists the ever-prescient temptation of quantifying everything by propositions and qualifying reality by the bare premises of the human ego.

Is it possible that God decided to make Himself known acurately through human language, even if it isn't comprehensive?

How would one determine (which require, again, the above-referenced incorporation of "proofs") that the picture is "accurate" (which will require an independent value against which to judge the evidence)?

thegreatswalmi said...

interesting thinking, ED. I've been thinking of language lately as iconic, rather than absolutized, that is, a sign or symbol pointing to God rather than a descriptive. That said, however, the beauty of Christology is that Christ made visible, finite, for finite creatures what the character of the invisible, infinite God is. in linguistic terms for me, that means that the eternal Word became for us a temporal word that our temporal words may have the ability to point to the eternal (your point #2, i think). All ethereal, i know, but it's a process :) thanks for the sharpening.

Anonymous said...

One of the reasons Christianity is appealing to me is because of the doctrine of Incarnation. This is essentially your point # 2. God 'realizes' how difficult it is for humans to wrap their language around him (e.g. the masculine pronoun I just had to use), and therefore gives us the ultimate divine anthropomorphism in Jesus. Which is why you are correct that Christians owe it to themselves to speak of God in Christological terms.

Exist-Dissolve said...

tim--

First, let me say thanks for the footnotes!

Of course, of course. If it weren't for our conversations back at your blog, I doubt that I would have ever found the impetus for this post. So I will say "thank YOU."

Also, I don't have any major problems with what you have said here, except I wonder if you are falling prey to the absolutizing nature of language by implying that language is necessarily this way. In other words, you have gave it more ontological weight than I think is necessary.

Yes, this is probably inevitable. It's like relativism--saying that there are no absolutes is an absolute statement, and what not. However, I think there is value in making tentative statements about the deficiency of propositional language, even if this tentative statement itself borders on or even countenances propositional language.

Moreover, I don't think all languages are equal in absolutizing. Western languages are more susceptible to this due to the structure of our language: subject, predicate, verbs, and nouns. There are some languages that don't have nouns, which makes it less likely and harder to absolutize since everything is a verb or "event." See, I had to use a noun!

This is an interesting thought. I would like to see you do a post further explicating this idea. Please?!

I also would press you by saying that language does more than describe or refer; it has the ability to "show." Wittgenstein is a master at doing this. The best example I can think of is attempting to summarize a play you just saw on Broadway. You can repeat lines and the plot, even word for word, but something is still lost in this "translation."
The play isn't irrational because it can't be summarized in language--far from it, since we understood the play when we saw it. It is simply irreducible in its form! I think language as a whole has this kind of "form."


This is a great point, and I would probably agree. However, if we are speaking of "show," we have moved definitively beyond the confines of propositional language (which is a good thing, in my opinion). After all, in light of your example, I cannot tell you what the performance of Les Misarables is "about" in an absolute, propositional way. Rather, my statements will proceed along the lines of "show," i.e., relating to you the experience which I have had of Les Mis, and effect which this had on me in determining the language which I will utilize in "describing" it to you. In this way, I think your subsequent experience of Les Mis, even if qualitatively different than mine, will still interact on a mutually consistent level. Alternatively, imagine if I propositionalized my language and said, "this, definitively, is what Les Mis is "about""! If you went to it and had a different experience, you would be forced to conclude, on the basis of my utilization of language, that I was 1.) lying or 2.) ignorant. However, because of the position which I have placed you in through my use of language, your only recourse to counter my language is to offer equally hegemonic statements.

This "showing" that language does is the most important part when speaking about God, I think.

I entirely agree.

One more thing. Nice job "showing" the problem with "correspondence" and independent means of measurement. It took me a while to get to that point, and it was a difficult road. The hard part, for me at least, is not backsliding into it!

Very true. It is hard for all of us, for I think the natural tendency in langauge is to do this very thing.

Also, to think we can use an independent measure is exactly what Aquinas thinks we must NOT do as this would betray our createdness, at least the way I and others read him. Our "mode of signification" matches our finite status. Hence, we must say more and more about God. This is why the Summae could never be finished.

What if we were to say less and less? Just a thought.

BEAST said...

Re language and the divine....as my old granny used to say Jaysus feckin H Christ ...... you have given me a headache....I think that about wraps it up :-)

Brent Railey said...

hey exist,

I'm going to link your blog on mine. Hopefully, if I ever get some time to write, I'll comment on some of your stuff on there.

If I do, I would like your email address so that I could privately let you know that I will do so.

I would enjoy some dialogue with you...you would definitely will be huge challenge.

you can contact me @ brent@brentrailey.com

Anonymous said...

I am not sure if Exist divulges his E-mail address on the 1st date...maybe it evicerates from his mystique. I've perused briefly through your entry "Human Language and The Divine", I can't make an informed appraisal yet but it does present an interesting outlook. Given the anthropomorphic language in Holy Writ, this shall prove interesting...
In Christ,
Sam

Jerry Grace said...

Exist~dissolve,

I don't know who you are but I just read your comments, more of an essay than comments over at Calvinist Gadfly followed by reading your post on language here.
Never have I read clearer thinking and writing and defining in better terms for me what I know I believe and why.
Jerry

SCHALZ said...

BEHOLD, A Blog!
...perspicuously contradictory...
BUT NEVER THE LESS A BLOG.
I wondered some if "perspicuously contradictory" somewhat defines blogging in general.
I guess there are ways to iron things out.
Belief..Proof... whats left to define?